This article will be discussing deeply about the Constitutional History of India. And this article composed of two parts i.e., Part I & Part II. Part I contains meaning and concept of Judicial Activism, Theories of Judicial Passivism and Activism, Judicial Self-Restraint versus Judicial Activism, Evolution and development of Judicial Activism in India, and Judicial Activism and Separation of power.
PART - I
1. INTRODUCTION:
In 21st century all are witnessing a huge
shift in the global balance of power. As the mastery of the west degression,
the world is looking after the emerging powers of the new world order, like
India. India gets corner view in the world face due to its successful nourishment
of democracy and its tremendous economic growth, notwithstanding its cancerous
corruption and unstable infrastructure. The journey from being rolled by
British emperor for a long period to an independent sovereign country has not
been easy for India. There are three branches of the government in India such
legislative, executive and judiciary.
In 1922, Gandhiji said swaraj would not
be the gift of the British Parliament, but must emergence from ‘the wishes of
the people of India as expressed through their freely chosen representatives.’
He had expressed that Indians must shape their own destiny, that only in the
hands of Indians could India become herself. Twenty- four years later these words
were repeated during the opening session of the Constituent Assembly: they
were, some said, the Assembly’s origin; all agreed that they were its
justification.
The Constituent Assembly, brought into
being by the will of the Indian people and, in the last scene of the last act,
with the help of the British, drafted a constitution for India and it was
adopted in 26th January 1949 and come into force in the year 26th
January 1950. In the Constituent Assembly Indians were, for the first time in a
century and a half, responsible for their own governance. They were, at last,
free to shape their own destiny, to pursue their long-proclaimed aims and
aspirations, and to create the national institutions that would facilitate the
fulfilment of these aims.
In the words of B.R. Ambedkar-
‘By independence we have lost the
excuse of blaming the British for anything going wrong. If hereafter things go wrong,
we will have nobody to blame except ourselves.’
Jawaharlal Nehru believed, ‘This cannot
be done by the wisest of lawyers sitting together in conclave; it cannot be
done by small committees trying to balance interests and calling that
constitution-making; it can never be done effectively when the political and
psychological conditions are present, and the urge and sanctions come from the
masses.’
There are three branches of the
government in India such legislative, executive and judiciary.
The role of a judge and executive has
been clearly stated even during the Vedic period:
“Rajno hi raksadhi krtah parasvadayinah
sathah
Bhtya bhavanti prayena tebhyo
reksedimah prajah”
Thus, meaning the king should give the
charge of the protection of the subjects to such officers who are virtuous,
well tried, qualified and from respectable families.
The traditional role of the Judge has
been envisaged as that of an impartial arbiter who hears the forensic debate
before him and renders judgment without ever stepping into the arena of debate.
Lately, however, it has become fashionable for Judges to jump into the fray and
actively participate in the debate by supporting one side or the other and this
process masquerades under the felicitous name "judicial activism".
The expression ‘Judicial Activism'
signifies the anxiety of courts to find out appropriate remedy to the aggrieved
by formulating a new rule to settle the conflicting questions in the event of
lawlessness or uncertain laws.
Under the Constitution of India, the
three branches of the government, namely the Legislative, Executive and the
Judiciary, have been assigned their own separate roles. It is when the
Judiciary steps into the shoes of the Executive or the Legislature and embarks
on the work of law making rather than interpreting laws, it can be deemed to be
judicial activism.
Black’s Law Dictionary explains very well:
“Judicial activism is judicial
philosophy which motivates judges to depart from strict adherence to judicial
precedent in favour of progressive and new social policies which are not always
consistent with the restraint expected of the appellate judges. It is commonly
marked by decisions calling for social engineering and occasionally these
decisions represent intrusions in the legislative and executive matters.”
Before the twentieth century, legal
scholars squared off over the concept of judicial legislation, that is, judges
making positive law. "Where Blackstone favoured judicial legislation as
the strongest characteristic of the common law, Bentham regarded this as a
usurpation of the legislative function and a charade or miserable sophistry.
John Austin, rejected Bentham's view and defended a form of judicial
legislation in his famous lectures on jurisprudence.
Judicial activism is an upgraded form
of judicial review. Judicial review means overseeing by the judiciary of the
exercise of power by other co-ordinate organs of government with a view to
ensuring that they remain confined to the limits drawn upon their powers by the
Constitution. The practice of judicial review of legislation was extended by
Britain to colonies like India.
Later, when India got independence,
this debate continued in the Constituent Assembly also. The debates show that
the makers of the Constitution wanted a limited judicial review. Most of them
were admirers of the Westminster model of democracy and wanted the courts in
India to interpret the Constitution so as to cause minimum interference with
the legislature. In their opinion, a single integrated judiciary, along with a
uniform system of laws was essential to maintain the unity of the country.
Apart from being the conscience-keeper of the Constitution and the protector of
fundamental rights of the people, the framers wished to equip the judiciary
with powers which would enable it to "keep the charter of Government
current with the times and not allow it to become archaic or out of tune with
the needs of the day". While the provisions relating to the judiciary were
being drafted, there was general agreement on the issue that if independent
India were to achieve a social revolution, the judiciary would have a vital
role to perform and would therefore have to be well equipped for the purpose.
According to Justice V.G. Palishikar,
judicial activism can be defined as the process of law-making by judges. It
means an active interpretation of existing legislation by a Judge, made with a
view to enhance the utility of that legislation for social betterment. Judicial
activism is different from judicial pessimism which means interpretation of
existing provisions of law, without an attempt to enhance its beneficial
aspects by so interpreting the existing law to advance and progress the
beneficial extent of that legislation.
Judicial institutions have a sacrosanct
role to play in a constitutional democracy like India. Under Article 32 a
person can approach the Supreme Court for violation of any of his fundamental
rights as Article 13(2) also states that if a law passed by the state affects a
fundamental right, it may be declared null and void by the Supreme Court. The
High Courts are empowered with wider jurisdiction to entertain any petition not
only for the enforcement of fundamental rights alone but also for any other purpose.
The Supreme Court can also decide whether Parliament or State Legislature has
made any law beyond its allotted powers. Even Parliament can enlarge
jurisdiction and powers of the Supreme Court with respect to any matters in the
Union List by enacting law to this effect and also through law give it power to
use it writ jurisdiction under clause (2) of Article 32 for any other purpose.
Further, power is vested in the Supreme Court to pass such decree or order as
is need for doing justice in any case or matter pending before it. This
provision containing inherent powers of the court contains no limitation
regarding the case or circumstances which necessitates the court to exercise
its power nor does it lay down any conditions to be satisfied before such power
is exercised. But the courts itself through various judgments have said that
Article 142 could not be used to build a new edifice where none existed earlier
so to achieve something indirectly, which could not be achieved directly.
The role of Judiciary as it arguably
bears a larger share of the immediate responsibility for preserving and
defending the indispensable liberal dimension of the democratic regime than do
the two branches in spite of having no control over the sword or purse. In this
duty lies the best claim to the legitimacy that the courts can muster when they
extend their writ in an activist fashion.
In the context of Indian experience,
when this job of tailoring was adhered to by the Indian Judiciary, it was
alleged as ‘judicial anarchy’ judicial over-activism or judicial despotism. Few
critics, albeit labelled Judiciary as a ‘third chamber’ and ‘a super
executive.’ It is alleged that Judiciary has usurped the authority of
legislative and executive organs of the government. The opponents criticize
Judiciary as anti-democratic and counter majoritarian.
One of the very important principles of
just democratic governance is the application of Constitutional limits on the
extent of government power. These limits include conducting periodic elections,
granting civil rights, and promoting an independent judiciary, which allows
citizens to seek protection of their rights and redress government functions.
These limits help to make branches of government accountable to each other and
to the people. An independent judiciary is must for safeguarding the rule of Law
and is, therefore, vital facet of good governance.
“A judge must be of sterner stuff. His mental
equipoise must always remain firm and undeflected. It is essential that a judge
should not allow his personal prejudice to go into the decision- making. A
closed mind is antithetical to fair hearing. Prejudice tends to corrupt the
ability to exercise independent judgment. It has a tendency to intrude upon a
free mind and may influence the outcome.”
One of the essential features of the
democratic republic established by the Indian Constitution is division of power
between the three important wings of the State. The three wings are expected to
operate in their respective fields so that democratic governments, both at the
Centre and the States can function to fulfil the noble objectives enshrined in
the preamble to the Constitution. As early as in 1951. In re Delhi Laws case
(1951) the Supreme Court noted that though there are no specific provisions
in the Constitution vesting legislative powers exclusively in the legislature
and the judicial power in the judiciary, the essence of the doctrine of
separation of powers was implicit in the constitutional scheme. Later in Indira
Gandhi case in 1975 "separation of powers" was treated as a
part of the basic structure of the Constitution.
The philosophy of justice-social,
economic, political spelt out in the Preamble and article 38 of the
Constitution is to be imbibed in culture and life of people not only by
Judiciary but also by other organs of the State, hence, the importance of other
two organs should not be over-shadowed by the role of judiciary.
Even Dr. B.R. Ambedkar in his speech
before the Constituent Assembly expressed his views regarding putting checks on
the authority of the various organs of the Government. To quote: “In fact, the
purpose of a Constitution is not merely to create the organs of the State but
to limit their authority, because, if no limitation was imposed upon the
authority of the organs, there will be complete tyranny and complete
oppression. It would result in utter chaos.
As originally enacted, the Constitution
of India provided for a Supreme Court with a Chief Justice and 7 judges. In the
early years, a full bench of the Supreme Court sat together to hear the cases
presented before them. As the work of the Court increased and cases began to
accumulate, Parliament increased the number of judges from the original 8 in
1950 to 11 in 1956, 14 in 1960, 18 in 1978, 26 in 1986 and 31 in 2008. As the
number of the judges has increased, they have sat in smaller benches of two or
three (referred to as a division bench) — coming together in larger benches of
five or more (referred to as a constitution bench) when required to settle
fundamental questions of law.
In 2008, then Union Law Minister, H.R.
Bharadwaj, explained the motivation for increasing the number of judgeships in
the Supreme Court from 26 to 31 as follows:
“It has not been possible for the Chief
Justice of India to constitute a five-Judge Bench on a regular basis to hear
cases involving interpretation of constitutional law as doing that would result
in constitution of a smaller number of Division Benches which in turn will
result in delay in hearing of other civil and criminal matters.”
Despite increases in the number of
judgeships, the pressure of the Court’s backlog remains so great that it
continues to be difficult to constitute the requisite number of constitutional
benches. As a result, matters of public importance continue to be decided by
smaller benches of 2-3 judges. One example is a recent judgment on the legality
of euthanasia – a complex issue concerning difficult questions of
constitutional law, which was decided by a two-judge bench. Another example is
the decision regarding the constitutionality of state sponsored militia in the
state of Chhattisgarh, which was delivered by a two-judge bench.
In the early years, the Supreme Court
interpreted the role of the Judiciary merely as determining in accordance with
narrow procedural rules. In A.K. Gopalan v. State of
Madras, the Supreme Court remarked, “In India the position of the
Judiciary is somewhere in between the Courts in England and the United States.
But our Constitution, Unlike the American Constitution, does not recognize the
absolute Supremacy of the Court over the legislative authority in all respects,
for outside the restricted field of constitutional limitations our parliament
and the State Legislature are Supreme in their respective legislative fields
and in that wider field there is no scope for the Court in India to play the
role of the Supreme Court of the United States.” This perception changed by the
time of Golak Nath case (1957), where the Supreme Court declared that
fundamental rights could not be derogated from even by an amendment to the
Constitution. Six years later, in Kesavananda Bharati
case (1973), while overruling Golak Nath case, the court evolved
another far-reaching doctrine under which Parliament was denied the power to
amend the Constitution in a manner that violated its ‘basic structure’. The
Supreme Court could not deny judicial review even by a constitutional amendment.
The first event that helped it gain
legitimacy was the emergency of 1975. The 1977 elections saw the overwhelming
defeat of the Congress party. The Janata party came to power. It immediately
dismantled most of the amendments inserted during the emergency and also put in
place some constitutional safeguards aimed at ensuring that the emergency
provisions in the Constitution are not misused.
2. MEANING AND CONCEPT OF JUDICIAL
ACTIVISM:
Judicial Activism is a term used for the unconventional
role played by the court when it gives value judgments and grants relief to the
aggrieved person or persons according to its moral and social sense of justice
in a situation where statutory law is silent or even contrary. It has also been
defined by some jurists as “non-interpretive judicial review.”
In Britain, where there was no written
constitution and the Parliament was supreme, the role of the courts was to
interpret the statutes. The courts were neither supposed to twist and turn the
language of the laid statutory provisions nor add or delete words from it, as
it could ruin the will of parliament that was supreme.
On the other hand, in countries with
written Constitutions, like U.S.A and India, it is not the legislature which is
supreme but it is the Constitution. Since, the task of interpreting the words
of the constitution is in the hands of the courts, the judiciary has more say
than their counter-parts in England. The first reported use of the term
'judicial activism' was by Arthur M Schlesinger in an article on the Supreme
Court of the United States in the January 1947 edition of Fortune magazine.
This was Roosevelt's Supreme Court.
The words 'judicial activists' appeared
on top of the second page of the article referring to Justices Black, Douglas,
Murphy and Rutledge. They were contrasted with 'Champions of Self Restraint' –
Frankfurter, Jackson and Burton. Justice Reed appeared next to a photograph of
Chief Justice Vinson above the title 'Balance of Power'. No definition of
'judicial activist' was offered in the article. However, Schlesinger sought to
characterize the conflict he perceived between the two groups in a way that gave
content to his coined term. The activist group, as he saw them, believed the
Supreme Court could play an affirmative role in promoting the social welfare.
The 'Champions' advocated a policy of judicial self-restraint, where one group
saw the court as an instrument to achieve desired social results, the second
saw it as an instrument to permit the other branches. Definitions and
Expressions government to achieve the results the people want for better or for
worse. In so characterizing the conflict, Schlesinger acknowledged the legal
realism underpinning the Black/Douglas view which derived from ideas
particularly dominant at Yale Law School. The Yale thesis, as he outlined it,
was that judging is a matter of reverse engineering from result to reasons. On
that theory: A wise judge knows that political choice is inevitable; he makes
no false preteens of objectivity and consciously exercises the judicial power
with an eye to social results.
3. THEORIES OF JUDICIAL PASSIVISM AND
ACTIVISM:
Judicial passivism and judicial
activism are contending and opposite theories of judicial attitude towards the
construction of statutes and there are arguments galore for and against these
two paradigms. The former concept emanates from the pure theory of separation
of powers and is predicated on a declaration theory of judicial functions which
assigns to courts the role of declaring what the law is and nothing more (jus
dicere). Proponents of this school do not go beyond written laws as
they believe that the legislature has written what is meant and meant what is
written – ita scriptum est (it is so written). They
are not concerned even if literal interpretations of statutes lead to
absurdity, hardship or injustice. They are also opposed to vesting courts with
discretionary powers, because the discretion of a judge, cautioned Lord Camden,
is the law of tyrants – always unknown, different in different men, causal and
depending on Constitution, temper and passion – and that in the best it is
often caprice, while in the worst it is every vice, folly and passion. Judicial
passivism is also called the bureaucratic tradition in which judges stick
tenaciously to the written text treated as ex cathedra.
On the other hand, judicial activism is
rooted in the concept that the end of any law is to arrive at justice, and if
literal construction occasions injustice it defeats the very purpose for which
the law was enacted.
Ordinarily, a judge is considered an
activist when (s)he does not go by the literal meaning of the statute but gives
effect to what, in her/his opinion, is congruous with the spirit of the law.
The Harper Collins Dictionary of American Government and Politics
defines it as the ‘making of new public policies through the decisions of
judges’. According to The New Dictionary of Cultural Literacy, it is
synonymous with the term ‘broad construction’ which the dictionary defines as a
‘theory of interpretation of the Constitution that holds that the spirit of the
time, the values of the justices, and the needs of the nation may legitimately
influence the decisions of a court, particularly the Supreme Court.
4. JUDICIAL SELF-RESTRAINT VERSUS
JUDICIAL ACTIVISM:
The concept of judicial review has
changing dimensions. To begin with, it is a product of judicial self-restraint.
But sometimes it invites activism. The terms judicial restraint and judicial
activism describe the degree of assertiveness of judicial power. Judges are
said to exercise judicial restraint when they have closeness to statutes and
previous cases in reaching their decisions; and they are said to exercise
judicial activism when they are apt to interpret existing laws and rulings more
loosely and interject their own values in the court decisions.
5. EVOLUTION AND DEVELOPMENT OF
JUDICIAL ACTIVISM IN INDIA:
The term “judicial activism”
came into currency sometime in the twentieth century to describe the act of
judicial legislation i.e., Judges making positive law. Although, the underlying
debate on judicial activism has been around since the days of Blackstone and
Bentham.
In India, the Regulating Act of 1773,
which symbolised the new concept of partnership between the Crown of England
and the East India Company, was the first essay in constitution-making for
India by the British Parliament. The Act created a Supreme Council in Bengal,
comprising the Governor-General and four councillors, which was vested with
chief executive authority over the other two provinces of Bombay and Madras. A
Supreme Court was also founded consisting of a Chief Justice and three judges.
However, the Regulating Act did not spell out the functions of the Supreme
Court clearly, which brought it into fierce conflict was the Supreme Council
which complained that the judges aimed at running a parallel government.
Berating the encroaching spirit of the judges a document of 1781 reads:
They have subjected every zamindar in
the country to their jurisdiction. They have granted writs of ejectment against
persons who have bought estates by the order of the Governor-General and
Council. They have ordered a writ of habeas corpus against the Naib Subha who
would have executed it, to avoid the consequences of such a measure, entreated
the Chief Justice to suspend the execution of the writ.
The collision between the Council and
the court reached hideous proportions threatening to tear asunder the lifelong
friendship between Warren Hastings and Sir Elijah Impey, the then Chief
Justice. In May 1780 Impey complained that he was being sacrificed to a union
between Hastings and Philip Francis. Hastings, however, successfully appeased
the Chief Justice by giving him supervisory power over the working of the
district courts.
Judicial review of legislative acts was
in vogue in the British colonies including India, since colonial legislatures
were not supreme as they derived their powers from the legislations enacted by
the British Parliament. Thus, the Indian courts exercised the power of judicial
review of legislation from the first Act by the British Parliament, enacted in
1858. The Calcutta High Court introduced the principle of judicial review in
the following words:
The theory of every government with a
written Constitution forming the fundamental and the paramount law of the
nation must be that an Act of legislature repugnant to the Constitution is
void. If void, it cannot bind the courts, and oblige them to give it effect;
for this would be to overthrow in fact what was established in theory and make
that operative in law which was not law.
The study of India reveals that the
glimpses of judicial activism were visible, even during the pre-independence
colonial era, in various judgments of the Privy Council which had the
jurisdiction to review the decisions of the Company’s courts and the Crown’s
courts in colonial India. In Emperor v. Sibnath Banerjee (1945),
the Privy Council held that the Court can investigate the validity of orders
passed under Section 59 (2) of the Government of India Act, 1935. Judicial
review of the Privy Council however ended with the abolition of the Privy
Council jurisdiction Act on 10th October, 1949.
The High Commissioner for India v.
I.M. Hall (1948), is another case where the Privy Council incorporated the
principles of ‘reasonable opportunity to the heard’ within the meaning of
Section 240 (3) of the Government of India Act, 1935. Judgments given by the
Federal Court constituted under the Government of India Act, 1935 in Niharendu
Dutt Majumdar v. Emperor (1942), is yet another example of an activist
judiciary. Here, the Federal Court held that mere criticism or even ridicule of
the Government does not amount to sedition unless the Act was calculated to
undermine respect for the Government so as to make people cease to obey it so
that only anarchy can follow. However, the Federal Court constituted under the
Government of India Act, 1935 mainly played the role of a literal interpreter.
This was because the Constitution of 1935 had no specific chapter on the Bill
of Rights and wide discretionary powers were conferred on the executive.
6. JUDICIAL ACTIVISM AND SEPARATION OF
POWER:
The ultimate goal of our constitution,
enunciated by our worthy founding fathers, in its preamble is to secure welfare
state. For achieving this goal, the constitution has created three organs - the
Legislature, the Executive and the Judiciary.
A bland justification for the judicial
activism is that courts must ensure that justice is done. In this process the
boundaries between the Legislature, the Executive and the Judiciary are
breached leading to the violation of the doctrine of separation of powers.
The question is how to ensure justice.
The Roman sentential fiat justicia ruat coelum caused some misconception as it
is translated to mean ‘let justice prevail though the heavens fall’.
There is an opinion that the
translation of ‘justicia’ into modern ‘justice’ is actually a
mistranslation. In fact, for the Romans, justice meant their system of law, fiat
jus ruat justiciam, ‘let the law prevail though justice may fall’. This
doctrine can be carried to the extreme as was done by a Maltese judge. Malta is
a small island which did not have room for more than one judge. In the
eighteenth century, there was a judge named Cambro. One early morning while he
was looking out of the window, he saw a man running and another frantically
chasing him. Ultimately, the victim was overtaken just under the window and
brutally stabbed with a knife. Just then the assailant saw a constable at some
distance and fled, leaving the knife in sheath in the wound. Soon afterwards a
baker happened to pass by with his basket of bread and found the victim lying
dead. As he tried to take the knife out of the wound, he saw a constable coming
towards him from a distance and was utterly terrified. He took the
blood-stained sheath of the knife in his hand, put it into his basket and
concealed himself beyond the entrance of a neighbouring house. Judge Cambro saw
all this with his own eyes. The constable arrived there and found the dead body
warm and still bleeding. He surmised that the murderer must be hiding somewhere
close. He searched and soon found the baker with his hands stained with blood
and the sheath in his basket fitted with the knife. Frightened, he lost his wit
and gave incoherent replies during interrogation. The baker was put on trial
before judge Cambro. Since no other judge was present, he had to try him. He
found that the circumstantial evidence against the baker was clinching enough
to convict him: he was found hiding near the place of occurrence immediately after
the murder, his hands were stained with blood and the weapon used for the crime
was found in his possession. Despite knowing personally that he was innocent,
the judge pronounced him guilty of murder as required by the law, sentenced him
to death, and the baker was executed. Later when the truth surfaced and the
real story came to be known, a horrified public demanded Cambro’s blood, but
there were jurists who supported and lauded his decision. He had done justice
according to law notwithstanding his personal knowledge that the baker was
innocent. On similar evidence he would have convicted anyone, and so he did
with the baker.
Confrontation between different wings
of government is not the result of clarity or ambiguity. It is a function of
the struggle for power, and every wing tramples on others when it is strong.
Antonio Gramsci has aptly described this: “The separation of power is a product
of the struggle between civil society and political society in a specific
historical period. In other words, there takes place within the society what
Croce calls the ‘perpetual conflict between Church and State’ in which the
Church is taken as representing the totality of civil society and the State as
representing every attempt to crystallize permanently a particular stage of
development, a particular situation. In this sense, the Church itself may
become State, and the conflict may occur between, on the one hand, secular
civil society, and on the other State/Church. Unity of the State in the
differentiation of powers: Parliament more closely linked to civil society: the
Judiciary power, between government and Parliament, represents the continuity
of the written law. Naturally all the three powers are also organs of political
hegemony, but in different degrees:
1. Legislature;
2. Judiciary;
3. Executive.
It is also to be noted that lapses in
the administration of justice make an especially disastrous impression on the
public: the hegemonic apparatus is more sensitive in the sector, to which
arbitrary actions on the part of the police and political may also be
referred.”
Aristotle believed that a good
government has to be a limited one. The political enlightenment French thinker,
Charles-Louis de Secondat, better known as Baron de Montesquieu, in his ‘Spirit
of Laws’ propounded the doctrine of the separation powers to maintain checks
and balance. He coined the term ‘separation of powers’ which became the guiding
principles of the constitutions of modern democratic states. The model is also
known at Trias Politica. Aristotle conceived a mixed government comprising the
noblest elements of monarchy, aristocracy and democracy, rating none as ideal.
The ancient Greeks developed it first and incorporated it into the
constitutions that governed their city-state, but it first became prevalent
during the Roman Republic. Its constitution expressly provided for separation
of powers. The state was divided into branches or estates, each with separate
and independent powers and areas of responsibility; the Executive, the
Legislature and the Judiciary. In his Oceana, James Harrington refined these
ideas to propose systems based on the separation of powers.
“There is no liberty where judicial
power is not separated from both legislative and executive power. If judicial
and legislative powers are not separated, power over the life and liberty of
citizens would be arbitrary, because the judge would also be a legislator. If
it were not separated from executive power, the judge would have the strength
of an oppressor.”
“Miserable indeed would be the case,
where the same man, or the same body, whether of the nobles or of the people,
to exercise those three powers, that of enacting laws, that of executing the
public resolutions, and that of judging the crimes or differences of
individuals.”
“All would be lost if the same man or
the same body of principal men, either of nobles, or of the people, exercised
these three powers: that of making the laws, that of executing public
resolutions, and that of judging the crimes or the disputes of individuals.”
Thus argued Montesquieu, the great
political philosopher of the Enlightenment, in favour of a system of governance
in which different branches of government exercise different powers to avoid
concentration of powers and preserve human liberty: -the Legislature should
make law, the Executive should execute it, and the Judiciary should settle
disputes in accordance with the law. This is the doctrine of separation of
powers. Though supporters of this doctrine believe that it protects democracy
by preventing the system from getting tyrannical, its critics refuse to accept
it and point out the success of mingling powers in parliamentary democracies.
Thomas Hobbes was its carping critic. Walter Bagehot subscribed to Hobbes’ view
and opposed the splitting of sovereignty. He thought that it was deleterious to
the health of the nation if at time of crisis one person is not in a position
to take a final decision. The mellowing translation of the “separation of
powers” doctrine into one of convenient “division of function” was not to arise
till persistent trends compelled it. Before the advent of democracy in its
present form, power was concentrated in the hands of the monarch. The monarch’s
power was absolute the unqualified. Actually, the role of the monarch evolved
from the idea of a single person acting as the leader of the community. The
history of Rome tells us that the emperors had absolute control over the empire
and its citizens. In Britain, Royal power was limited for the first time when
King John Lackland was forced to sign an agreement in June 1215 popularly known
as the Magna Carta.
No comments:
Post a Comment