DWORKIN’S THEORY OF JUSTICE
1. INTRODUCTION:
Judicial pronouncement has a very strong impact on
the lives of the citizens of a free country. Judgements create precedents or
case law and therefore create the future legal course of action. Ronald Dworkin states that the true propositions should relate to
the principle of fairness and justice because of the process providing
excellent constructive legal practice interpretation of the community.
Dworkin developed his
theory of adjudication in his seminal work ‘Taking Rights Seriously’
where is it is argued that it is the judge’s duty to discover that the parties
are, even when no settled rule disposes of the case. Dworkin refers to such
cases as ‘hard cases’ where there is a need to reply on principles in arriving
at a conclusion, as opposed to merely pedigreed rules. Judges, according to
Dworkin, can normally reach competent answers in ‘hard cases’ by consulting the
legal materials of their own jurisdiction that fall into the doctrinal
neighborhood of their immediate problem, guided by what he calls the principle
of ‘local priority’ which he defines as looking no further than the cases or
statutes dealing directly with the matter at hand; in formulating interpretive
arguments.
Constitutional morality is
not a new concept but has suddenly gained popularity in Indian jurisprudence. The use of this concept
can be traced to a number of recent landmark
judgments passed by Indian courts. Although the concept has been used as
a tool to ensure that an individual’s right is not taken away from him owing to societal
morality, this concept
has also been criticized on
various grounds. A prominent instance of this criticism is by Attorney General K.K.
Venugopal who raised concerns about the dangers
of this concept.
In this sense, it becomes important to ascertain what the judiciary
means by ‘Constitutional Morality’ and whether this ‘moral reading’ of
the constitution actually encroaches upon the legislature’s authority to make laws.
Having said
that, the aim of this paper is to analyze some of the Indian judgements that
have highlighted the concept of ‘Constitutional Morality’ with respect
to the Ronald Dworkin’s theory on law and morality.
For this purpose,
the paper will be
discussing in detail the concept of ‘Constitutional Morality’, describes
Ronald Dworkin’s theory on law and morality, presents an analysis of case law
with respect to Dworkin’s theory and the conclusion.
2. CONCEPT OF CONSTITUTIONAL MORALITY:
According to Dr. Ambedkar, Constitutional morality would mean effective coordination between conflicting interests of different people and the administrative cooperation to resolve them amicably without any confrontation amongst the various groups working for the realization of their ends at any cost.
Constitutional
morality has been regarded as a paramount reverence for the constitution.
Constitutional morality provides a principled understanding for unfolding the
work of governance. It specifies norms for institutions to survive and an
expectation of behavior that will meet not just the text but the soul of the
Constitution. It also makes the governing institutions and representatives
accountable.
The concept of constitutional morality is inexplicit in nature. It has not been given any concrete definition as such, neither in
the constitution nor in any case laws. The words ‘constitutional morality’ finds no mention
in the constitution of India and yet, it has been used by the judiciary
as a justification for many of its arguments. Another interesting point to note
is that when the constitutional provisions mention morality, they only mention
‘public morality’ which is, in fact, contrary to constitutional morality. Yet, the courts
have read this as constitutional morality and said that it shall prevail over societal morality
‘Constitutional Morality’ is not purely a common law concept. It does find
mention in some constituent assembly debates. Dr. Bhim Rao Ambedkar, in one of
the constituent assembly debates highlighted the importance of this concept.
Quoting the English historian, George Grote, he said:
“The diffusion of constitutional morality,
not merely among the majority
of any community but
throughout the whole, is the indispensable condition of a government at once
free and peaceable; since even any powerful and obstinate minority may render
the working of a free institution impracticable, without being strong enough to
conquer ascendency for themselves.
By constitutional
morality Grote meant a paramount reverence for the forms of the Constitution,
enforcing obedience to authority acting under and within these forms yet
combined with the habit of open speech, of action subject only to definite
legal control, and unrestrained censure of those very authorities as to all
their public acts combined too with a perfect confidence in the bosom of every
citizen amidst the bitterness of party contest that the forms of the
Constitution will not be less sacred in the eyes of his opponents than in his own."
In other words, this would
mean that the constitutional values shall be supreme and would be given
precedence while deciding the constitutional validity of any statute. In the
absence of constitutional morality, the operation of a constitution, no matter
how carefully written, tends to become arbitrary, erratic, and capricious.
In context of
the above said, it also becomes important to trace the need for the establishment of this concept. This
has been discussed by Andre Beteille, in her book, ‘Democracy and its
Institutions’, wherein she talks about how Ambedkar felt the lack of a
living democratic tradition in India. Given the inequalities that existed in
the Indian society in terms of class and
caste, he believed that the constitution alone could not create an egalitarian
society. Thus, to be effective, constitutional laws have to rest on a
substratum of constitutional morality.
3. RONALD DWORKIN’S THEORY ON LAW AND MORALITY:
Dworkin, unlike Hart,
believes that there exists a connection between law and morality. This is
because, in addition to rules, law also contains some non-rule standards. These
non-rule standards are called principles and policies. These principles and
policies have a dimension of ‘weight and importance’ attached to them.
Principles and policies
are different from each other. A principle is a standard to be
observed, not because it will advance or secure an economic, political, or social
situation, but because
it is a requirement of justice or fairness or some other dimension of morality. A policy, on
the other hand, is that kind of standard that sets out a goal to be reached,
generally an improvement in some economic, political, or social feature of the community. However, according to
Dworkin, there is no set standard to determine what these principles are since these keep changing
from time to time. Moreover,
principles describe rights
while policies describe goals. This can be further understood by the example of
case given by Dworkin himself. Arguments of principle justify
a political decision
by showing that the decision respects or secures some
individual or group right. The case of Riggs v. Palmer. The question before the
court was whether a murderer could inherit the will of the victim. The law was such that it did not carve
out any exception for murderers. Thus, on the face of it, the murderer should
be entitled to the property. However, the court applied the principle that ‘no
man should profit from his own wrong’ and hence,
the murderer could
not inherit from his own victim. In this sense, the rule did
not exist before the case was decided. Once the case is decided, the principle
used to interpret a particular rule, gives the rule a new interpretation for
the current case and all future cases to follow.
Dworkin’s ‘rights as
trump’ theory stems from this wherein he argues that rights have a ‘threshold
weight’ against community goals. If we are to respect individual rights, he
argues, they must not be capable of being squashed by some competing community
goals. The central question in any
litigation is whether the claimant has a ‘right to win’; not whether the
community’s interests should be satisfied.
Following
this, Dworkin also articulates the role of judges i.e., discretion when faced
with a legal issue. For this purpose, he invents a superhuman judge with superhuman skill and acumen called Hercules. When Hercules is faced with a ‘hard case’,
he has to apply legal principles. Being a superhuman judge, he ought to look
into the legislative purpose of a particular statute. He accepts that statute
have the general power to create and extinguish legal rights and that judges have the general duty to follow
earlier decision of their court or higher courts whose rationale extends to the
case at bar.
Dworkin draws
from the assumption that there is a written constitution in Hercules land, and
he is faced with a legal issue. He might begin by asking why the constitution
has any power at all to create or
destroy rights. The constitution sets out a general political scheme that is
sufficiently just to be taken
as settled for reasons of fairness. Citizens
take the benefit
of living in a society whose institutions
are arranged and governed in accordance with that particular political scheme.
Thus, while deciding
a case, Hercules will have to see which theory
provides a better fit to the constitutional scheme as a whole.
Dworkin
compares deciding cases to writing chapters in a chain novel. Suppose a group
of writers are engaged in writing a novel. Some writers will write the first
chapter, some the second and so on. However,
in every subsequent chapter written by a writer,
there will be some
understanding of the chapter preceding it. Thus, every new chapter will be an
addition to the novel and will thus be coherent with the previous
chapters. In this sense, every
writer will bear the responsibility of interpreting
what the previous writer wrote and creating the next chapter. This, according
to Dworkin, is similar to how judges should decide hard cases. He or she must read through what other judges in the past have written, not simply to discover what these
judges have simply written, but to reach an opinion about what these judges
have collectively done. A judge’s duty is to interpret the legal history he
finds, not to make a better history. Moreover, there is always one ‘right
answer’ to every legal problem; it is up to the judge to find it. This answer
is ‘right’ in the sense that it coheres best with the institutional and constitutional history of the law. Legal argument and analysis is therefore interpretative in character. The judge, thus, exercises his discretion while
interpreting what the previous judges have said.
4. CONSTITUTIONAL MORALITY IN INDIAN JURISPRUDENCE WITH RESPECT TO
DWORKIN’S THEORY:
This paper will now
towards analyzing Dworkin’s theory with respect to Indian judgements and how
they have used the concept of constitutional morality.
For this
purpose, this paper will be using some of recent landmark judgments including
Naz Foundation vs Government of NCT of Delhi and Ors, Navtej Singh Johar v.
Union of India, K.S. Puttaswamy vs Union of India, Indian Young Lawyers
Association & Ors. vs State of Kerala and Ors
Constitutional
morality can be classified as a non-rule standard. As mentioned in the preceding
discussion, the words ‘constitutional morality’ does not find any mention in
either the constitution or any other statute i.e., rule. This means that it
would be applied as a non-rule standard i.e., a principle. Moreover, it is not
that the concept of constitutional morality is purely a common law concept. To
justify the application of this concept, the judges have talked about how the
roots of the concept lie in the constituent assembly debates and what the
constitution makers intended. This can be seen in light of Dworkin’s argument on
the role of judges wherein he says that while deciding a case, the judges are
restricted with preceding case laws, established theories or any other material
which they think will lead them to the best answer to the legal issue before
them.
Dworkin says that there is
a connection between law and morality. Related to this is the distinction between
rule and non-rule
standard. However, In the case of constitutional morality, the rule and non-rule standard are not distinct from
each other but can be found within each other. This is because, the morality is
being derived from the law i.e., rule itself. This morality is not that of the public,
community or even a judge. This morality
flows from the constitution
only and paramount any other forms of ‘morality’.
Before moving
on to a case-to-case analysis of the concept, it is imperative to look into
some of the common aspects of the cases mentioned earlier. In all these judgments,
the courts have distinguished public morality from constitutional morality and
has held the latter to trump the former. They have said that the only
‘morality’ that would pass the test of compelling state interest is
‘constitutional morality’ and not ‘public morality’. This is an important
aspect of Dworkin’s ‘rights as trump’ theory which says that the main question
in a litigation is whether the claimant is entitled to win
and not because the community’s interests should be satisfied. The courts have
also opined that public disapproval is no ground to deny a person his
fundamental rights.
Coming first
to the Delhi High Court case of Naz Foundation v. Govt of NCT of Delhi which held that treating
consensual homosexual sex between adults as a crime is a violation of
fundamental rights protected by India's Constitution. One of the key aspects of
the judgment was the court’s use of ‘constitutional morality’. Before beginning
to apply the concept of constitutional morality to the issue at hand,
the court discussed the history of the doctrine.
The court, thus, attempts to establish a basis for using the concept. It
is not as if it is in isolation with legal history. Thus, conforming to the
boundaries within which judges are supposed to exercise their discretion, as
argued by Dworkin.
The court has also relied upon a South
African case called
The National Coalition for Gay and
Lesbian Equality v. The Minister of Justice. This case enforced the idea of
constitutional morality in the context of equal rights for homosexuals.
The 377 judgment goes a step further by holding constitutional morality as being
representative of the spirit of the constitution and its values. Chandrachud,
J. said that-
“The Preambular goals of
our Constitution which contain the noble objectives of Justice, Liberty,
Equality and Fraternity can only be achieved through the commitment and loyalty
of the organs of the State to the principle of constitutional morality. It is the concept of constitutional
morality which strives and urges the organs of the State to maintain such a
heterogeneous fibre in the society,
not just in the limited
sense, but also in multifarious ways.”
The
above extract is relating constitutional morality to the larger objective of
the constitution as enshrined in the preamble. As mentioned in foregoing
discussion, Dworkin argues that judges need to see which theory best fits in
the constitutional scheme as a whole. Constitutional morality, as a concept,
talks about the supremacy of the constitution.
It is
interesting to note that in the Sabrimala Temple judgement, both the
minority and majority opinion were supported by applying the principle of
constitutional morality. This is indicative of the interpretative character of
legal analysis and argument as stated by Dworkin. Going by Dworkin’s argument,
it can be inferred that two judges can have differing opinions on the same
legal issue due to the different ways in which they would view or interpret the
same principle. Let us contrast the two and see if and how this contrast fits
into Dworkin’s argument pertaining to the interpretative power possessed by the
judges.
An extract
from the majority
view delivered by the then chief justice,
Dipak Misra is as follows-
“In
the public law conversations between religion and morality, it is the
overarching sense of constitutional morality which has to prevail. While the Constitution recognizes religious beliefs and faiths, its purpose is to
ensure a wider acceptance of human dignity and liberty as the ultimate founding
faith of the fundamental text of our governance. Where a conflict arises, the quest for human dignity, liberty and
equality must prevail. These, above everything else, are matters on which the
Constitution has willed that its values must reign supreme.”
While interpreting constitutional morality, Misra, J. also relied on a particular extract from the case of Government of NCT of Delhi v Union of India, which highlighted the importance of constitutional morality. This reliance can be related to what Dworkin lays down as being part of the ‘role of judges’ while deciding a case. This previous stated version of constitutional morality can be inferred to act as a boundary within which the judges have to operate while presenting a legal analysis. However, as stated in section three, how the judge would interpret this precedent is up to his or her sense of morality.
An extract from the minority
opinion delivered by Justice Indu Malhotra is as follows-
“Constitutional Morality in a pluralistic society and secular
polity would reflect that the followers of various
sects have the freedom to practice their faith in accordance with the tenets of their religion. It is
irrelevant whether the practice is rational or logical. Notions of rationality cannot be invoked
in matters of religion by courts. Constitutional morality requires the
harmonization or balancing of all such rights, to ensure that the religious
beliefs of none are obliterated or undermined.”
From the above two strands
of minority and majority opinions, it can be observed that the concept of
constitutional morality is considerably wide in its scope. We can situate Dworkin’s ‘interpretative character’
argument within this wide scope. However, Dworkin also suggests that due to the
existence of what earlier judges have opined, the judges deciding future cases
have a boundary within which they are required to produce judgments. Given the
wide scope of this concept, these boundaries become faint giving the judges
immense leeway to interpret.
5. CONCLUSION:
An analysis of case laws
pertaining to constitutional morality shows that the concept is not confined to
any one constitutional provision, rather represents the spirit of the
constitution as a whole. This has given
considerable authority to the judiciary
to interpret the concept by taking
various strands of arguments, even if they are contradictory to each other. Dworkin
suggests that although judges
have to present
their legal analysis
within restrictions imposed
on them in the form of previous case laws, it is up to them as to how
they interpret them. However, there is no fixed limit to interpretation as suggested
by Dworkin. The concept of constitutional morality does conform to Dworkin’s
theory is some respects but has its own unique features at the same time.
Dworkin's elucidation may
not be accepted by legal parlance, but his contributions are nevertheless
phenomenal. Jurisprudential schools in general and positivism in particular,
are struggling with the problem of subjectivity and seeking theories which can
be verified externally. Though, the human factor does play an indubitably
important part in decision-making. Legal positivism seems to underplay the
essential validity of sociological jurisprudence, and unduly isolates the moral
tenets of natural law. Dworkin’s view seems to be closer to reality by
including political morality in his decision-making process. On a careful
analysis of the problem, he appears to be somewhere in the middle of legal
realism, natural law and positivism. His stress on the extent to which the
selection of rules and determination of their applicability to facts is
controlled by principles penetratingly shakes-up the ‘ruling theory’ of
positivism. His claim that political morality plays a pivotal role in
determining the selection of principles serves to reunify law and morality.
These contributions of Prof. Ronald Dworkin are substantial and praiseworthy,
but the insistence on the presence of preexisting rights in institutional
history yielding one right answer is not descriptive of the legal arena or the
world.
No comments:
Post a Comment